It's Still Not the End of History
The Atlantic
Most of us in the West are liberals, whether we
admit it or not. We want equal rights for all, reject racial differences,
cherish the freedom of worship while preserving the freedom to disagree, and
seek an economic order that suits the ambitions of the individual. But there’s
a growing sense that liberalism isn’t delivering at home and that it’s not as
popular as we think it ought to be in the developing world. The problem is that
hubris has blinded its defenders to the crisis consuming liberalism’s identity,
leaving them unable or unwilling, to respond to pressing challenges around the
world.
Twenty-five years ago this summer, Francis Fukuyama
announced the “end of history” and the inevitable triumph of liberal capitalist
democracy. His argument was simple: Democracy would win out over all other
forms of government because the natural desire for peace and well-being set
nations on a path to progress from which it was impossible to divert. If a
state—even a Communist state—wished to enjoy the greatest prosperity possible,
it would have to embrace some measure of capitalism. Since wealth-creation depends
on the protection of private property, the “capitalist creep” would invariably
demand greater legal protection for individual rights.
As many critics pointed out, Fukuyama’s logic was a
bit too reminiscent of the pseudo-Hegelian historical determinism that Marxists
and Fascists deployed to disastrous effect earlier in the 20th century, but
when his article appeared in The National Interest, it was hard to
disagree with him. The Berlin Wall was about to fall, the Soviet Union was
collapsing, and the world was clamoring for the consumerist boom in an orgy of
free-market excitement. Everything seemed to suggest that only liberal
capitalist democracy allowed people to thrive in an increasingly globalized
world, and that only the steady advance of laissez-faire economics would
guarantee a future of free, democratic states, untroubled by want and
oppression and living in peace and contentment.
History isn't over, and neither liberalism nor democracy is ascendant.
Today, it’s hard to imagine Fukuyama being more
wrong. History isn’t over and neither liberalism nor democracy is ascendant.
The comfy Western consensus he inspired is under threat in ways he never
predicted. A new Cold War has broken out. China’s “Marxist capitalism” suggests
you can have wealth without freedom. And the advance of ISIS may herald a new,
state-oriented Islamic fundamentalism.
But most disturbingly, the connection between
capitalism, democracy, and liberalism upon which Fukuyama’s argument depended
has itself been broken. In the wake of the credit crunch and the global
economic downturn, it has become increasingly clear that prosperity is not, in
fact, best served either by the pursuit of laissez-faire economics or by the
inexorable extension of economic freedoms. Indeed, quite the opposite. As
Thomas Piketty argues in Capital in the Twenty-First Century, free
markets have not only enlarged the gap between rich and poor, but have also
reduced average incomes across the developed and developing worlds. In the
countries hardest hit by the recession—such as Greece and Hungary—voters have
turned away from precisely that conception of liberalism that Fukuyama believed
they would embrace with open arms. Across Europe, economic interventionism,
nationalism, and even open racism have exerted a greater attraction for those
casting their democratic votes than the causes of freedom, deregulation, and
equality before the law. Liberal capitalist democracy hasn’t triumphed.
Instead, the failures of capitalism have turned democracy against liberalism.
In turn, liberalism’s intellectual self-identity has been left in tatters.
Sensing that Fukuyama’s titanic argument has hit
something of an iceberg, liberal theorists have desperately been trying to keep
the ship afloat. A raft of books have hit the shelves trying to breathe new
life into liberalism, amongst which Larry Siedentop’s Inventing the
Individual and Edmund Fawcett’sLiberalism: The Life of an Idea stand
out. Both accept that Fukuyama’s hubris has been exposed by recent events, and
are under no illusions about the challenges that liberalism faces. But instead
of addressing those challenges head-on they have turned to the past for solace
and validation. By labeling an arbitrary set of ideals “liberal” and trying to
demonstrate how they have supposedly triumphed over all challengers down the
centuries, they seek to craft a new historical narrative capable of “proving”
the inherent righteousness of liberalism. Since “liberal” ideas have always
triumphed, Siedentop and Fawcett argue, they are manifestly right, and while
things might not be working out so well now, the logic of history shows that
they will prevail in the end.
Instead of addressing those challenges, liberal theorists have turned to
the past for solace and validation.
Leaders across the political spectrum have been
quick to adopt this form of historical determinism. In Britain, David Cameron’s
center-right government is proudly liberal, and has not been afraid to use
history to mold the next generation of voters into an appropriately liberal
form. Earlier this year, his former education minister, Michael Gove, tried to
recast the First World War as an example of liberal values triumphing over
Germany’s proto-fascism, and as “proof” of the undoubted righteousness of the
sort of militant liberalism that neoconservatives adore. Closer to home,
Hillary Clinton—now in the first stages of a barely denied run for the White
House—has adapted a similar outlook in the realm of foreign policy. Looking
back at the great ideal of America as established by the Founding Fathers
through rose-tinted spectacles, she has subtly distanced herself from Barack
Obama’s cautious realism abroad and instead used discrete references to the
past to justify aggressively exporting liberal values across the globe as often
as possible. Given that history has “proved” how great liberalism was in
previous battles against tyranny, the argument goes, liberalism will inevitably
win out if we pick enough fights and put enough muscle behind it.
But while this new liberal historicism may have a
certain rhetorical appeal, it fails to convince. Instead of recognizing the
weakness of Fukuyama’s original approach, Siedentop, Fawcett, Cameron, and
Clinton have simply dusted down the same old historical determinism, just
without the economics. It isn’t any more convincing than when Fukuyama tried
it.
It was the great liberal philosopher Karl Popper
who first exposed the weaknesses of historicism as a mode of political
justification in his devastating critique of Marxist and fascist determinism.
It is ironic that his arguments now apply to the liberalism he sought to
defend. Following Popper’s argument, it’s easy to see at least two fundamental
logical problems with the historicist approach to liberalism. First is the
claim that anyone in the past who expressed any degree of egalitarianism or
concern for individual conscience is a liberal. The idea that there is a
straight line of human progress that leads from Saint Paul through Luther, the
Philosophes, and Lloyd George to Jack Kennedy is patently absurd: They all had
different definitions of freedom and what it ought to accomplish. Second, the
idea that there is a “historical law” guiding the development of societies is
fanciful. Even if there were some weird sort of pattern which suggested that
“liberal” ideas did indeed “win out” in the past, it wouldn’t be anything more
than a mere curiosity. It wouldn’t prove anything about liberalism in itself,
nor would it say anything about the future. It would just tell us what happened
before. To read meaning or predictive power into any pattern in the past is, in
fact, about as intellectually respectable as reading tea leaves.
As the weaknesses
of the new liberal historicists’ arguments show, liberalism is struggling to
recover from its post-Fukuyama malaise because its defenders are just being too
lazy. Siedentop, Fawcett, Cameron, and Clinton seem to assume that everyone
with an ounce of sanity must be a liberal, and that there is
hence no need to defend liberalism against its shortcomings. But no amount of
retrospective back-patting will convince those who simply don’t think the same
way. It’s no wonder, given their intellectual arrogance, that so many liberals
are surprised when large parts of the world rejects them—or that people spurn
their wise counsel when markets collapse and life savings are threatened by the
accidents of free-market capitalism.
If liberalism is to survive and flourish, it has to
be rescued from Fukuyama’s grasp and from the perils of historical determinism.
It has to be defined and defended all over again. This of course raises the
question of what liberalism actually is—and it’s notable that so many liberals
skip this step in debate as though it was unimportant. In a recent issue of Foreign
Policy dedicated exclusively to reevaluating Fukuyama’s legacy, the
unresolved problem of “the liberal identity” was conspicuous by its absence.
Article after article foundered in their attempts to defend liberal
alternatives to populism or socialism precisely because they offered no
satisfactory post-Fukuyama understanding of liberalism. But it is impossible to
defend liberalism against its critics without making it clear precisely what it
stands for. Skeptics can hardly be won over if liberals can’t tell them what
they are being won over to or how it differs from the uninspiring mess created
by Fukuyama and his continuators.
Surrounded by the confused, jargon-ridden babble of
political commentators today, it is perhaps easy to forget that liberalism is
defined by a commitment to liberty. At root, liberty is a concept grounded in
the individual. It is the freedom to be all that one is, to actualize the
fullness of one’s potential as a human being endowed with the capacity for
creativity and the ability to make autonomous value judgments for ourselves.
But it is impossible to defend liberalism without making clear what it
stands for.
It is, of course, true that liberty can be read many
ways. As Isaiah Berlin observed, there is positive liberty, the freedom to do
something; and there is negative liberty, the freedom from something; and
depending on circumstances, one or the other can appear to be of greater
importance. But while this distinction has tended to dominate debates in
political philosophy since the Second World War, it is perhaps more useful to
think back to the writings of Voltaire and the earliest Encyclopédistes and
to remind ourselves that liberty in its purest form—both positive and
negative—can be thought of as the realization of man’s inherent dignity as a
human being.
This is more than just a matter of high-flown
words. The concept of human dignity has two important implications, both of
which were recognized by Cicero as far back as the first century B.C. but seem
to have been forgotten today. The first is that we all share the same degree of
dignity: No one has any less potential than any other, and no one’s humanity is
any less pronounced than anyone else’s. The second is that our humanity imposes
upon us the same basic needs. By virtue of our nature, we all require food,
shelter, clothing, security, and a range of other basic goods necessary for
sufficiency and survival. Though deceptively simple, these implications have
profound meaning when we consider how individual liberty is to be translated
into a social and political construct. If the liberty of each person is to be
maintained and maximized, the principles of equity and the common good must be
embedded in the structure of society. And since society is structured above all
by law, the law must reflect these precepts. To have liberty is hence to live
according to laws grounded on equity and the common good; and where law
deviates to even the smallest degree from either, it necessarily becomes the
instrument of private or factional interests, and liberty is lost.
Such liberty is, however, dependent upon the
morality of the citizenry, especially those in office. While law may structure
society, it is only the will of governors and people that gives it its
character and force. It is only if everyone recognizes the dignity of the human
person that they will recognize the inherent value of equity and the common
good, and strive to defend and preserve not only their own liberty, but also
that of all others in their society using law. As soon as the commitment to
human dignity breaks down, society becomes a jungle in which it is everyone for
himself; self-interest dominates, law becomes partial, and tyranny supplants
liberty.
In short, a liberal politics must be a moral
politics. Liberalism will not work if too much emphasis is placed on total
human autonomy at the expense of all others, nor if it is obsessed with
materialism and consumerism. In contrast to the Fukuyama model of yoking
liberal values to economic self-interest—a combination that, when given free
rein, has often damaged society at large in recent years—a model that
emphasizes human dignity allows for a more positive, relevant kind of politics
that constantly struggles to assert itself. Instead of encouraging us to rest
easy in the assurance that liberalism will certainly triumph, a conception of
liberty based on human dignity recognizes that there is nothing inevitable
about its success. While each of us may wish to be free as an individual, it
shows that individual freedom is dependent on us all being free; and that means
that we all have to cling to our shared humanity, our shared dignity.
If liberalism has a future, therefore, it lies not
in Fukuyama’s shattered determinism or the more recent liberal historicism of
Siedentop, Fawcett, and Clinton, but in each of us. It lies not in economics,
or the tides of history. It lies in the recognition of the worthiness of
humanity itself.
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario